亚洲免费av电影一区二区三区,日韩爱爱视频,51精品视频一区二区三区,91视频爱爱,日韩欧美在线播放视频,中文字幕少妇AV,亚洲电影中文字幕,久久久久亚洲av成人网址,久久综合视频网站,国产在线不卡免费播放

        ?

        A Constructive Exposition on Simple Forcings and Countable Forcings

        2017-05-15 10:56:01ZHUHuilingZHENGFudan
        關(guān)鍵詞:數(shù)理邏輯可數(shù)偏序

        ZHU Huiling, ZHENG Fudan

        (Guangzhou College, South China University of Technology, Guangzhou 510800, Guangdong)

        A Constructive Exposition on Simple Forcings and Countable Forcings

        ZHU Huiling, ZHENG Fudan

        (GuangzhouCollege,SouthChinaUniversityofTechnology,Guangzhou510800,Guangdong)

        In this paper, we explain two classes of forcings: simple forcings and countable forcings. A couple of examples that mathematician are interested in are studied as special cases of forcing. General theorems about these two classes are proved.

        simple forcing; countable forcing; partial order; dense embedding; models

        1 Introduction

        In modern set theory, forcing is an effective technique in obtaining independent results. Since its discovery by Cohen[1], the application of forcing has been extended to many branches of mathematics. In particular, those branches with infinite objects. However, the highly technical feature of forcing also kept it away from being understood for many mathematicians. There are a couple of standard textbooks about forcing, for instance, [2-3]. These textbooks provide a detailed treatment of forcing and are suitable for those with basic knowledge about set theory. However, people believe that although the general theory of forcing is not an open research problem, it remains an open exposition problem, as illustrated in [4]. Therefore, logicians attempted to make the system of forcing more accessible to mathematicians who are interested in independent proof. For example, [4] put much effort in making forcing “transparent”. We wish to follow the line and make explanations of some more facts of forcing. The beginners of forcing are referred to [5-7] for basic notions and notations. Readers with interests in applications are referred to [8-9].

        2 Simple Forcings

        A trivial forcing consists of a singleton. Such a forcing will not affect the ground model at all. Mathematicians are familiar with many kinds of partial orders, for instance, finite partial orders, linear orders and lattices. In a sense that we will explain below, these partial orders are all simple, as they are reduced to a trivial forcing.

        Forcing extends models of set theory, preserving certain features of the initial model and violating some others. In the study of forcing, it is crucial to analyze the properties of given partial orders. The general theory of forcing thus involves comparing two partial orders, finding similarities as well as differences between them.

        The following theorem can be found in [2]:

        Theorem 2.1 If there is a functionf:→satisfying:

        1)Orderpreserving:Ifp≤p′,thenf(p)≤f(p′);

        2)Density:Foranyq∈,thereissomep∈withf(p)≤q;

        3)Non-triviality:Ifpandqareincompatible,thenf(p)andf(q)areincompatible.

        Thenandgeneratesthesamegenericextension.

        Ifanytwoanyelementsofarecompatible,thencanbedenselymappedintoatrivialforcing.

        Corollary2.2Suchafunctionfiscalledadensemapping.Aninjectivedensemappingisusuallycalledadenseembedding.Wealsosaythatandareforcingequivalent,witnessedbyf.

        ProofConsider{{?},=},whichisanexampleofatrivialforcing.Letf(p)=?foranyp.ThenthefirsttworequirementsofTheorem2.1hold.Thethirdrequirementholdssincetheassumptionfails.

        Asaresult,anylinearorderorsemi-lowerlatticeisdenselymappedintoatrivialforcing.

        Afiniteforcingisactuallyatomic,namely,everyconditionextendstoanatom.Sinceeverygenericfilterhastoincludealltheatoms,ithastoincludethewholepartialorder.Thentheforcingistrivialbydefinability.

        3 Cohen Forcing

        The first and most notable forcing was Cohen forcing[1], which uses finite segments to approximate a real. Namely, the partial order is (2<ω,?). A maximal collection of conditions which are mutually consistent will define a function fromωto 2. In set theory, reals are identified with such functions. More precisely, any such function corresponds to an irrational number in the inteval (0,1). Associated with the product topology, such a space is called the Cantor space. There are other variations of the space of reals. For instance,ωωwith the product topology is called the Baire space.

        Cohen forcing is countable. In fact, any nontrivial countable partial orders yields the same generic extension. Though this is a known result, there is no text which present a direct construction. Therefore we explain it here in an accessible way by defining a dense embedding explicitly.

        4 Examples of Countable Forcings

        Before we proceed to the general case, let us start with some concrete examples.

        Theorem 4.1 There is a dense embeddingf:(4<ω,?)→(2<ω,?).

        Proof Letπ:4→22be a bijection. For instance,π(0)=〈00〉,π(1)=〈01〉,π(2)=〈10〉,π(3)=〈11〉. Definefas follows:

        It is obvious thatfis a nontrivial embedding.

        To show thatfis dense, letσ∈2<ω. Ifσhas an even length, letσ′=σ; otherwise, letσ′=σ⌒0. Letτ∈4<ωbe defined as:

        Thenf(τ)=σ′?σ.

        Theorem 4.2 The forcing (3<ω,?) can be densely embedded into (2<ω,?).

        Proof Fixπwithπ(0)=〈0〉,π(1)=〈10〉,π(2)=〈11〉. Let

        Notice that for everyσ∈2<ω, one can trace the digits from the root, find pieces of type 〈0〉, 〈10〉 or 〈11〉, and if the last remaining digit is 1, extendσwith a 0 to the tail. For instance, givenσ=〈0010110〉∈2<ω, considerτ=〈00120〉, thenh(τ)=σ. Givenσ=〈00101101〉, we first extend it toσ′=〈001011010〉, and letτ=〈001201〉, thenh(τ)=σ′<σ.

        It is clear thathis a dense embedding.

        Theorem 4.3 There is a dense embedding from (ω<ω,?) into (2<ω,?).

        Proof First fix a codingπ:ω→2<ω. A canonical coding is the following:π(0)=?,π(1)=〈0〉,π(2)=〈1〉,π(3)=〈00〉,π(4)=〈01〉,π(5)=〈10〉,π(6)=〈11〉 etc.

        Defineg:(ω<ω,?)→(3<ω,?) as follows:

        gis clearly injective and order preserving.gis actually surjective and hence dense. One can trace the digits in 3<ωand find the suitable preimage. For instance, the sequence 〈0020210221211〉 has preimage 〈315026〉.

        Combininggwith the dense embeddinghin Theorem 4.2, one gets a dense embedding from (ω<ω,?) into (2<ω,?).

        5 The General Theorem

        In this section, we prove the general theorem that two nontrivial countable forcings are actually equivalent.

        A forcing partial order is usually assumed to be both separative and atomless. These requirements are used to keep the forcing away from being trivial. Namely, an atom in a forcing adds no generic object as it contributes no diversity to the forcing. Also, if a forcing is non-separative, then it contains some segments of linear ordering, which can be deleted without affecting the property of forcing.

        Theorem 5.1 For every separative atomless countable partial order,thereisacountablepartialorder,whichcanbedenselyembeddingintobothand(2<ω,?).

        WeprovefirstalemmaontheCohenforcing.

        Lemma5.2Foranyσ∈(2<ω,?), 2≤n≤ω,thereisamaximalantichainbelowσwithcardinalityn.

        ProofForeachn<ω,considertheset

        InFigure1,theunderlinednodesformamaximalantichainofsize4.

        Ifn=ω,considertheset

        InFigure2,theunderlinednodesformamaximalantichainofsizeω.

        ProofofTheorem5.1List={sm:m∈ω}.Firstly,wefindamaximalantichainA0={pn:n∈I0},whereI0isanindexset.Makesurethatthereissomepn≤s0andA0hasatleast2elements.

        ItisclearthatA1isanantichain.Itisactuallymaximal.Foranyr,thereissomepncompatiblewithr.Letq≤pn, q≤r.Letpnkbecompatiblewithq,sayq′≤q, q′≤pnk.Thenq′≤rwitnessthatrandsomepnkarecompatible.

        Inductively,atstepn,oneconstructamaximalantichainbelowanyconditionfoundatthepreviousstep.AndletAncollectalltheseconditionsfoundatstepn.Byinduction, Anisamaximalantichain.

        Thisprocesscanbecarriedonasisseparativeandatomless:atstepm,thereissomea∈Am-1suchthatsnandaarecompatible.letr≤sm, r≤a.Sinceisatomless,wemayassumethatr

        Nowdefine=∪{Am:m<ω}.Themappingfromtoissimplyinclusion.Toseethatisadensesubforcing,letsm∈,thenthereissomea∈Am?suchthata≤sm.

        Themappingfrominto(2<ω,?)isdefinedasfollows:firstidentifyA0withamaximalantichainin(2<ω,?).ThiscanbeguaranteedbyLemma5.2,as2≤|A0|≤ω.Inductively,identifyAnwithamaximalantichainin(2<ω,?)whilepreservingthepartialorder.

        Toseethedensity,onecanalsodealwithconditionsin(2<ω,?)diagonally,aswedidwith.

        Remark5.3Theaboveproofisactuallythetypical“backandforth”argument,whichiseffectiveindealingwithcountableobjects.

        6 Futher Problems

        Inthissection,weconsidersomeproblemsforfuturestudy.

        1)Aretheresemi-upperlatticeswhichareusefulinthesenseofforcing?

        2)Foragivenalgebraicstructure,forinstance,aringorafield,isthereacanonicalwaytoassociateaforcingtoit?

        3)Fortopologicalspaceswithdifferentseparability,isthereaclassificationtheoryinthewayofforcing?

        [1] COHEN P J. The independence of the continuum hypothesis. I.[J]. Proc Natl Acad Sci,1963,50:1143-1148.

        [2] JECH T. Set theory[C]//Springer Monographs in Mathematics. New York:Springer-Verlag,2003.

        [3] KUNEN K. Set theory[C]//Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics,102. Amsterdam:North-Holland Publishing,1980.

        [4] CHOW T Y. A beginner’s guide to forcing[C]//Communicating Mathematics,479. Providence:Am Math Soc,2009:25-40.

        [5] JECH T. Multiple forcing[C]//Cambridge Tracts in Mathematics,88. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press,1986.

        [6] JECH T. What is … forcing?[J]. Notices Am Math Soc,2008,55(6):692-693.

        [7] JECH T. Set theory, with particular emphasis on the method of forcing[C]//Lecture Notes in Mathematics,217. New York:Springer-Verlag,1971.

        [8] TODORCHEVICH S, FARAH I. Some applications of the method of forcing[C]//Yenisei Series in Pure and Applied Mathematics. Moscow:Lycee,1995.

        [9] JECH T. Abstract theory of abelian operator algebras:an application of forcing[J]. Trans Am Math Soc,1985,289(1):133-162.

        關(guān)于單純力迫和可數(shù)力迫的構(gòu)造性闡述

        朱慧靈, 鄭馥丹

        (華南理工大學 廣州學院, 廣東 廣州 510800)

        解釋了2類力迫,即單純力迫和可數(shù)力迫.將數(shù)學家經(jīng)常遇到的幾類偏序作為力迫的特殊情況加以研究.證明了關(guān)于這2類力迫的一般性結(jié)論.

        單純力迫; 可數(shù)力迫; 偏序; 稠密嵌入; 模型

        O144.3

        A

        1001-8395(2017)01-0018-04

        2015-10-03

        國家自然科學基金(11401567)

        朱慧靈(1985—),男,副教授,主要從事數(shù)理邏輯及其應用的研究,E-mail:zhuhl02@gmail.com

        Foundation Items:This work is supported by National Natural Science Foundation of China (No.11401567)

        10.3969/j.issn.1001-8395.2017.01.003

        (編輯 周 俊)

        Received date:2015-10-03

        2010 MSC:03E17; 03E35; 03E50

        猜你喜歡
        數(shù)理邏輯可數(shù)偏序
        基于數(shù)理認知的數(shù)理邏輯類益智玩具設計研究
        玩具世界(2024年2期)2024-05-07 08:15:50
        可數(shù)一致連續(xù)偏序集的序同態(tài)與擴張
        基于有限辛空間的一致偏序集和Leonard對
        相對連續(xù)偏序集及其應用
        漢語名詞的可數(shù)與不可數(shù)
        一致可數(shù)可加馬氏鏈不變測度的存在性
        數(shù)理邏輯在工程技術(shù)中的應用探析
        東方教育(2017年9期)2017-07-19 10:49:17
        可消偏序半群的可消偏序擴張與商序同態(tài)
        圣誕快樂
        謎語大集合
        久久综合五月天| 色一情一乱一伦一视频免费看| 在熟睡夫面前侵犯我在线播放| 91精品一区国产高清在线gif| 九九视频在线观看视频6| 人妻被猛烈进入中文字幕| 国产午夜精品综合久久久| 亚洲av日韩av激情亚洲| 草草久久久无码国产专区| 日韩一区二区超清视频| 一区二区三区四区免费国产视频| 亚洲综合国产成人丁香五月激情 | 九一精品少妇一区二区三区| 亚洲日韩小电影在线观看| 98久9在线 | 免费| 亚洲综合网站精品一区二区| 人妻少妇偷人精品视频| 人妻无码一区二区三区| 欧美日韩中文国产一区| 狠狠色欧美亚洲综合色黑a| 青青草手机免费播放视频| 女人和拘做受全程看视频| 欧美aⅴ在线| 国产在线精彩自拍视频| 日本饥渴人妻欲求不满| 性欧美暴力猛交69hd| 国产激情一区二区三区成人免费| av网站免费观看入口| 在线看片免费人成视频电影| 亚洲自拍另类制服在线| 99久久免费精品色老| 国产精品亚洲第一区二区三区| 欧美精品中文字幕亚洲专区| 久久99精品久久久66| 国产精品亚洲一二三区| 国产精品中文久久久久久久| 99福利在线| 亚洲一区二区三区精品久久| 国产免费又爽又色又粗视频| 五十路熟久久网| 女同视频网站一区二区|